Too Short for a Blog Post, Too Long for a Tweet 154
Here are a few excerpts from a book I recently read, "Scalia Speaks: Reflections on Law, Faith, and Life Well Lived," by Antonin Scalia.
One’s
work is not to be taken lightly. Not only because it is a necessary
means of putting bread on the table, but because it is perhaps the
single most influential factor (apart from your own free will) in
determining what kind of people you will be. There is a profound
spiritual connection between a human being and his or her work. What we
do for a living is at once and the same time an expression of our
identity, and a formation of it. It is less true that we are what we eat
than that we are what we do to eat.
Lawyers
really have no more interest than anyone else—and no more expertise
than anyone else—in what the substance of our laws should be. If you
want to know whether deregulation is good or bad, ask an economist. If
you want to know whether indeterminate prison sentences are good or bad,
ask a criminologist or penologist. What lawyers are good at, what
lawyers are for, is implementing these decisions in a manner, through a
process, that is fair and reasonable.
I
fear that this characteristic of ours, which is perhaps our most
distinctive and profound characteristic, will never be understood by the
layman. It is the source of the most common criticism of lawyers: that
we can argue both sides of a case. But of course we can—because except
to the extent that a client’s interest may be involved, we as lawyers
have no interest in a particular outcome, but only in assuring that the
outcome be fairly and intelligently arrived at and clearly and precisely
expressed!
Movement
is not necessarily progress. More important than your obligation to
follow your conscience—or at least prior to it—is your obligation to
form your conscience correctly.
The
reason, of course, is that a bill of rights has value only if the other
part of the constitution—the part that really “constitutes” the organs
of government—establishes a structure that is likely to preserve,
against the ineradicable human lust for power, the liberties that the
bill of rights expresses. If the people value those liberties, the
proper constitutional structure will likely result in their preservation
even in the absence of a bill of rights; and where that structure does
not exist, the mere recitation of the liberties will certainly not
preserve them. So while it is entirely appropriate for us Americans to
celebrate our wonderful Bill of Rights, we realize (or should realize)
that it represents the fruit, and not the roots, of our constitutional
tree. The rights it expresses are the reasons that the other provisions
exist. But it is those other humdrum provisions—the structural,
mechanistic portions of the Constitution that pit, in James Madison’s
words, “ambition against ambition,” and make it impossible for any
element of government to obtain unchecked power—that convert the Bill of
Rights from a paper assurance to a living guarantee. A crowd is much
more likely to form behind a banner that reads “Freedom of Speech or
Death” than behind one that says “Bicameralism or Fight”; but the latter
in fact goes much more to the root of the matter.
The
consequences of this phenomenon in the United States have not been
good, either for judging or for democracy. As for judging: to get
confirmed to a federal court in the United States, one must be nominated
by the president and confirmed by the Senate. This used to be, for the
most part, a fairly routine process. But it has become a major
battleground for the political parties and the interest groups, a major
issue in every presidential campaign. When an individual is nominated
for a federal judgeship, few Americans care whether the nominee will
approach each case with an independence of mind, or a reasoned process
of decision-making. Americans care instead about results. Will the
nominee, for example, uphold the right to abortion on demand? This trend
is an unfortunate one, but it is entirely understandable. Once the
vocation of a judge is conceived of as the vocation of the common-law
judge, why shouldn’t Americans care what that judge thinks about the
moral issues of the day? The result is a nomination process that
politicizes the judiciary.
The
judge as legislator has also not been good for democracy. When the
vocation of a judge is reduced to simply selecting the best rule,
remarkable power is placed in the hands of a few persons who are barely
accountable for their decisions. In my country, most judges are given
life tenure, and it is almost impossible to get a judge impeached. This
was originally designed to give judges some insulation from the public
indignation that often accompanies unpopular decisions. But when the
vocation of a judge is more akin to that of a lawmaker, such insulation
seems remarkably inapt. Moreover, there is no reason to suspect that the
justices on my court, for example, are particularly good
representatives of the views that a majority of Americans hold. We all
live in Washington, D.C., for goodness’ sake—we are totally out of touch
with America! And we are all lawyers. Since when would a majority of
Americans think that a group of nine lawyers from elite law schools
should be entrusted with deciding the “best rules” for all of our
countrymen to live by?
Another
criticism of originalism—perhaps the most common one—is that it
petrifies the law. Thus, the approach set up in opposition to
originalism is sometimes called the approach of the “living
Constitution”—a constitution that evolves as the needs of society
require. Seems very attractive. But if you think that the proponents of a
living Constitution are trying to bring you flexibility and the power
to change, you should think again. A constitution is designed to provide
not flexibility but rigidity—and that is precisely what the proponents
of a living Constitution use it for. The originalists’ Constitution
permits expansive change when the people desire it. Do you want the
death penalty? Elect those who will impose it. Do you abhor the death
penalty? Elect those who will abolish it. And you can change your mind.
If you find that the murder rate goes up after the abolition of the
death penalty, elect those who will reinstitute it. If, however, the
living constitutionalists have their way and declare the death penalty
unconstitutional, the people’s power to choose is eliminated. No death
penalty, period.
That is
what has happened, of course, with abortion. The Constitution says
nothing about the subject. It neither forbids (as the pro-choice people
claim) nor requires (as the pro-life people claim) restrictions upon it.
For two centuries, laws in every state prohibited it, but now, under a
living-Constitution theory, it cannot be prohibited. No use trying to
persuade your fellow citizens one way or the other about the subject. It
has been taken off the democratic stage. And that is, of course,
precisely what those who argued for Roe v. Wade desired to achieve. So
don’t love the living Constitution because it will bring you flexibility
and choice; it will bring you rigidity, which is precisely what it is
designed for.
The
Europeans, and most other countries of the world, look at our system
with something approaching disbelief. One House passes a bill, and the
other House, which may be controlled by the other party, disapproves it.
Or they both approve it, but the president exercises a veto. This is,
they solemnly pronounce, a recipe for gridlock. It is indeed, and our
Framers would say hooray. It is precisely that dispersal of power that
they believed would be the primary bulwark of minorities against the
tyranny of the majority. It does not take much to stop legislation that
grievously injures a determined minority. It is easy to throw a monkey
wrench into the works. By and large, only legislation with broad support
will emerge from the complex system.
There
is of course a great irony in this new practice of selecting justices
on the basis of what kind of Constitution the People desire. The whole
purpose of the Bill of Rights is to protect individuals against the
wishes of the people; and in enforcing the restrictions contained in
those provisions, the courts act in a decidedly anti-democratic
capacity. They tell the people that they cannot do what they would like
to do. Thus, to turn the interpretation of the Constitution over to
majority opinion is to place the Bill of Rights in the hand of precisely
the entity it was meant to protect against.
Comments